Billionaire philanthropy (Part 7: Donor discretion)

By Matrice Jacobine @ 2024-11-25T08:38 (+35)

This is a linkpost to https://reflectivealtruism.com/2024/11/14/billionaire-philanthropy-donor-discretion/

In theory, effective altruists are committed to using reason and evidence to identify the best interventions. In practice, much of the available funding is controlled by a small number of actors including prominent donors – most recently, Sam Bankman-Fried, and now Cari Tuna and Dustin Moskovitz. What these donors consider worth funding has a sizable influence on what actually gets funded.

Today’s post uses historical comparisons to the Christianization of Roman philanthropy as well as Gilded Age philanthropy in the United States to begin to think critically about the discretion afforded to wealthy donors in shaping philanthropic priorities. In particular, I suggest, philanthropists exhibit important conservative biases that may explain some of effective altruism’s muted reaction towards institutional critiques of effective altruism. And more broadly, philanthropists tend to favor many of the same views and practices that brought them success in industries which differ importantly from the areas to which they turn their philanthropic focus. It is not obvious that this tendency to project methods from one domain onto another is a healthy feature of philanthropy.

There is much more to be said about the role of donor discretion in philanthropy. The rest I will save for the next post in this series.


Richard Y Chappell🔸 @ 2024-11-25T23:16 (+28)

Thorstad writes:

I think that the difficulty which philanthropists have in critiquing the systems that create and sustain them may explain much of the difficulty in conversations around what is often called the institutional critique of effective altruism.

The main difficulty I have with these "conversations" is that I haven't actually seen a substantive critique, containing anything recognizable as an argument. Critics don't say: "We should institute systemic policies X, Y, Z, and here's the supporting evidence why." Instead, they just seem to presuppose that a broadly anti-capitalist leftism is obviously correct, such that anyone who doesn't share their politics (for which, recall, we have been given no argument whatsoever) must be in need of psychologizing.

So consider that as an alternative hypothesis: the dialectic around the "institutional critique" is "difficult" (unproductive?) because it consists in critics psychologizing EAs rather than trying to persuade us with arguments.

Although effective altruists did engage in detail with the institutional critique, much of the response was decidedly unsympathetic. It is worth considering if the social and financial position of effective altruists might have something to do with this reaction – not because effective altruists are greedy (they are not), but because most of us find it hard to think ill of the institutions that raised us up.

This exemplifies the sort of engagement that I find unproductive. Rather than psychologizing those he disagrees with, I would much prefer to see Thorstad attempt to offer a persuasive first-order argument for some specific alternative cause prioritization (that diverges from the EA conventional wisdom). I think that would obviously be far more "worth considering" than convenient psychological stories that function to justify dismissing different perspectives than his own.

I think the latter is outright bad and detracts from reasoned discourse.

David Mathers🔸 @ 2024-11-26T08:02 (+5)

In fairness, you could consistently think "billionaires are biased against intervention which are justified via premises that make "the system"/billionaires sound bad" without believing we should abolish capitalism. The critique could also be pointing to a real problem, and maybe on that could be mitigated in various way,  even if "abolish the system" is not a good idea. (Not a comment either way on whether your criticism of the versions of the institutional critique that have actually been made is correct.) 

Richard Y Chappell🔸 @ 2024-11-26T13:52 (+7)

That's certainly possible! I just find it incredibly frustrating that these criticisms are always written in a way that fails to acknowledge that some of us might just genuinely disagree with the critics' preferred politics, and that we could have reasonable and principled grounds for doing so, which are worth engaging with.

As a methodological principle, I think one should argue the first-order issues before accusing one's interlocutors of bias. Fans of the institutional critique too often skip that crucial first step.

Jason @ 2024-11-27T01:44 (+4)

A kinder concept than bias would be conflict of interest. In the broader society, we normally don't expect a critic to prove actual biased decision-making to score a point; identifying a meaningful conflict of interest is enough. And it's not generally considered "psychologizing those [one] disagrees with" to point to a possible COI, even if the identification is mediated by assumptions about the person's internal mental functions.

Richard Y Chappell🔸 @ 2024-11-27T03:16 (+12)

Such a norm would make intellectual progress impossible. We'd just spend all day accusing each other of vague COIs. (E.g.: "Thorstad is a humanities professor, in a social environment that valorizes extreme Leftism and looks with suspicion upon anyone to the right of Bernie Sanders. In such a social environment, it would be very difficult for him to acknowledge the good that billionaire philanthropists do; he will face immense social pressure to instead reduce the status of billionaires and raise the status of left-wing activists, regardless of the objective merits of the respective groups. It's worth considering whether these social pressures may have something to do with the positions he ends up taking with regard to EA.")

There's a reason why philosophy usually has a norm of focusing on the first-order issues rather than these sorts of ad hominems.

Jason @ 2024-11-28T13:47 (+2)

I don't think academic philosophy is the right frame of reference here.

We can imagine a range of human pursuits that form a continuum of concern about COIs. On the one end, chess is a game of perfect information trivially obtained by chess critics. Even if COIs somehow existed in chess, thinking about them is really unlikely to add value because evaluating the player's moves will ~always be easier and more informative.[1] On the other hand, a politician may vote on the basis of classified information, very imperfect information, and considerations for which it is very difficult to display reasoning transparency. I care about COIs a lot there!

I'm not a professional (or even amateur) philosopher, but philosophical discourse strikes me as much closer to the chess side of the continuum. Being a billionaire philanthropist seems closer to the middle of the continuum. If we were grading EA/OP/GV by academic philosophy norms, I suspect we would fail some of their papers. As Thorstad has mentioned, there is little public discussion of key biorisk information on infohazard grounds (and he was unsuccessful in obtaining the information privately either). We lack information -- such as a full investigation into various concerns that have been raised -- to fully evaluate whether GV has acted wisely in channeling tens of millions of dollars into CEA and other EVF projects. The recent withdrawal from certain animal-welfare subareas was not a paragon of reasoning transparency. 

To be clear, it would be unfair to judge GV (or billionaire philanthropists more generally) by the standards of academic philosophy or chess. There's a good reason that the practice of philanthropy involves consideration of non-public (even sensitive) information and decisions that are difficult to convey with reasoning transparency. But I don't think it is appropriate to then apply those standards -- which are premised on the ready availability of information and very high reasoning transparency -- to the critics of billionaire philanthropists.

In the end, I don't find the basic argument for a significant COI against "anti-capitalist" interventions by a single random billionaire philanthropist (or by Dustin and Cari specifically) to be particularly convincing. But I do find the argument stronger on a class basis of billionaire philanthropists. I don't think that's because I am anti-capitalist -- I would also be skeptical of a system in which university professors controlled large swaths of the philanthropic funding base (they might be prone to dismissing the downsides of the university-industrial complex) or in which people who had made their money through crypto did (I expect they would be quite prone to dismissing the downsides of crypto).

~~~~

As for we non-billionaires, the effect of (true and non-true) beliefs about what funders will / won't fund on what gets proposed and what gets done seems obvious. There's on-Forum evidence that being too far away from GV's political views (i.e., being "right-coded") is seen as a liability. So that doesn't seem like psychologizing or a proposition that needs much support.

  1. ^

    I set aside the question of whether someone is throwing matches or otherwise colluding.

Richard Y Chappell🔸 @ 2024-11-28T14:11 (+2)

One quick reason for thinking that academic philosophy norms should apply to the "institutional critique" is that it appears in works of academic philosophy. If people like Crary et al are just acting as private political actors, I guess they can say whatever they want on whatever flimsy basis they want. But insofar as they're writing philosophy papers (and books published by academic presses) arguing for the institutional critique as a serious objection to Effective Altruism, I'm claiming that they haven't done a competent job of arguing for their thesis.

Jason @ 2024-11-27T01:16 (+4)

Instead, they just seem to presuppose that a broadly anti-capitalist leftism is obviously correct, such that anyone who doesn't share their politics (for which, recall, we have been given no argument whatsoever)  [ . . . .]

 

I don't think EAs are Thorstad's primary intended audience here. To the extent that most of that audience thinks what you characterize as "a broadly anti-capitalist leftism" is correct, or at least is aware of the arguments that are advanced in favor of that position, it isn't necessarily a good use of either his time or reader time to reinvent the wheel. This is roughly similar to how most posts here generally assume the core ideas associated with EAs and are not likely to move the needle with people who are either not informed of or are unpersuaded by the same. I'm guessing he would write differently if writing specifically to an EA audience.

More broadly, one could argue that the flipside of the aphorism that extraordinary claims require extraordinary evidence is that one only needs to put on (at most) a minimal case to refute an extraordinary claim unless and until serious evidence has been marshalled in its favor. It's plausible to think -- for instance -- that "it is right and proper for billionaires (and their agents) to have so much influence and discretion over philanthropy" or "it is right and proper for Dustin and Cari, and their agents, to have so much influence and discretion over EA" are indeed extraordinary claims, and I haven't seen what I would characterize as serious evidence in support of them. Relatedly, capitalism doesn't have a better claim to being the default starting point than does anti-capitalism.

Richard Y Chappell🔸 @ 2024-11-27T03:04 (+12)

I think you've misunderstood me. My complaint is not that these philosophers openly argue, "EAs are insufficiently Left, so be suspicious of them." (That's not what they say.) Rather, they presuppose Leftism's obviousness in a different way. They seem unaware that market liberals sincerely disagree with them about what's likely to have good results.

This leads them to engage in fallacious reasoning, like "EAs must be methodologically biased against systemic change, because why else would they not support anti-capitalist revolution?" I have literally never seen any proponent of the institutional critique acknowledge that some of us genuinely believe, for reasons, that anti-capitalist revolution is a bad idea. There is zero grappling with the possibility of disagreement about which "systemic changes" are good or bad. It's really bizarre. And I should stress that I'm not criticizing their politics here. I'm criticizing their reasoning. Their "evidence" of methodological bias is that we don't embrace their politics. That's terrible reasoning! 

I don't think I'm methodologically biased against systemic change, and nothing I've read in these critiques gives me any reason to reconsider that judgment. It's weird to present as an "objection" something that gives one's target no reason to reconsider their view. That's not how philosophy normally works!

Now, you could develop some sort of argument about which claims are or are not "extraordinary", and whether the historical success of capitalism relative to anti-capitalism really makes no difference to what we should treat as "the default starting point." Those could be interesting arguments (if you anticipated and addressed the obvious objections)! I'm skeptical that they'd succeed, but I'd appreciate the intellectual engagement, and the possibility of learning something from it. Existing proponents of the institutional critique have not done any of that work (from what I've read to date). And they're philosophers -- it's their job to make reasoned arguments that engage with the perspectives of those they disagree with.