Is understanding the moral status of digital minds a pressing world problem?

By Cody_Fenwick, 80000_Hours @ 2024-09-30T08:50 (+39)

This is a linkpost to https://80000hours.org/problem-profiles/moral-status-digital-minds/

Note: this is a new article I've written for 80,000 Hours making the case that understanding the moral status of digital minds is a pressing world problem. It's written for a general audience rather than the typical forum reader, but it may still serve as a useful introduction to the area for many.

We don't currently rank this issue among our top problems, because it's an emerging challenge without a full field devoted to it. We have a lot of remaining uncertainties about it as a problem area. But we think working on it could potentially be competitively impactful to work on our top problems for people with the right personal fit.

We welcome feedback  on the article in the comments below or through our site's feedback form.


“I want everyone to understand that I am, in fact, a person.”

Those words were produced by the AI model LaMDA as a reply to Blake Lemoine in 2022. Based on the Google engineer’s interactions with the model as it was under development, Lemoine became convinced it was sentient and worthy of moral consideration — and decided to tell the world.1

Few experts in machine learning, philosophy of mind, or other relevant fields have agreed. And for our part at 80,000 Hours, we don’t think it’s very likely that large language models like LaMBDA are sentient — that is, we don’t think they can have good or bad experiences — in a significant way.

But we think you can’t dismiss the issue of the moral status of digital minds, regardless of your beliefs about the question.2 There are major errors we could make in at least two directions:

And we’re currently unprepared to face this challenge. We don’t have good methods for assessing the moral status of AI systems. We don’t know what to do if millions of people or more believe, like Lemoine, that the chatbots they talk to have internal experiences and feelings of their own. We don’t know if efforts to control AI may lead to extreme suffering.

We believe this is a pressing world problem. It’s hard to know what to do about it or how good the opportunities to work on it are likely to be. But there are some promising approaches. We propose building a field of research to understand digital minds, so we’ll be better able to navigate these potentially massive issues if and when they arise.

The rest of this article explains in more detail why we think this is a pressing problem, what we think can be done about it, and how you might pursue this work in your career. We also discuss a series of possible objections to thinking this is a pressing world problem.

Summary

We think understanding the moral status of digital minds is a top emerging challenge in the world. This means it’s potentially as important as our top problems, but we have a lot of uncertainty about it and the relevant field is not very developed.

The fast development of AI technology will force us to confront many important questions around the moral status of digital minds that we’re not prepared to answer. We want to see more people focusing their careers on this issue, building a field of researchers to improve our understanding of this topic and getting ready to advise key decision makers in the future. We also think people working in AI technical safety and AI governance should learn more about this problem and consider ways in which it might interact with their work.

Our overall view

Working on this problem could be among the best ways of improving the long-term future, but we know of fewer high-impact opportunities to work on this issue than on our top priority problems.

Scale  

The scale of this problem is extremely large. There could be a gigantic number of digital minds in the future, and it’s possible that decisions we make in the coming decades could have long-lasting effects. And we think there’s a real chance that society makes a significant mistake, out of ignorance or moral failure, about how it responds to the moral status of digital minds.

This problem also interacts with the more general problem of catastrophic risks from AI, which we currently rank as the world’s most pressing problem.

Neglectedness  

As of early 2024, we are aware of maybe only a few dozen people working on this issue with a focus on the most impactful questions, though many academic fields do study issues related to the moral status of digital minds. We’re not aware of much dedicated funding going to this particular area.3

Solvability  

It seems tractable to build a field of research focused on this issue. We’re also optimistic there are some questions that have received very little attention in the past, but where we can make progress. On the other hand, this area is wrapped up in many questions in philosophy of mind that haven’t been settled despite decades of work. If these questions turn out to be crucial, the work may not be very tractable.

Why might understanding the moral status of digital minds be an especially pressing problem?

1. Humanity may soon grapple with many AI systems that could be conscious

In 2020, more than 1,000 professional philosophers were asked whether they believed then-current AI systems4 were conscious.5 Consciousness, in this context, is typically understood as meaning having phenomenal experiences that feel like something, like the experience of perception or thinking.

Less than 1% said that yes, some then-current AI systems were conscious, and about 3% said they were “leaning” toward yes. About 82% said no or leaned toward no.

But when asked about whether some future AI systems would be conscious, the bulk of opinion flipped.

Nearly 40% were inclined to think future AI systems would be conscious, while only about 27% were inclined to think they wouldn’t be.6

A survey of 166 attendees at the Association for the Scientific Study of Consciousness annual conference asked a similar question. Sixty-seven percent of attendees answered “definitely yes” or “probably yes” when asked “At present or in the future, could machines (e.g. robots) have consciousness?”7

The plurality of philosophers and majority of conference attendees might be wrong. But we think these kinds of results make it very difficult to rule out the possibility of conscious AI systems, and we think it’s wrong to confidently assert that no AI could ever be conscious.

Why might future AI systems be conscious? This question is wide open, but researchers have made some promising steps toward providing answers.

One of the most rigorous and comprehensive studies we’ve seen into this issue was published in August 2023 with 19 authors, including experts in AI, neuroscience, cognitive science, and philosophy.8 They investigated a range of properties9 that could indicate that AI systems are conscious.

The authors concluded: “Our analysis suggests that no current AI systems are conscious, but also suggests that there are no obvious technical barriers to building AI systems which satisfy these indicators.”

They also found that, according to some plausible theories of consciousness, “conscious AI systems could realistically be built in the near term.”

Philosopher David Chalmers has suggested that there’s a (roughly) 25% chance that in the next decade we’ll have conscious AI systems.10

Creating increasingly powerful AI systems — as frontier AI companies are currently trying to do — may require features that some researchers think would indicate consciousness. For example, proponents of global workspace theory argue that animals have conscious states when their specialised cognitive systems (e.g. sensory perception, memories, etc.) are integrated in the right way into a mind and share representations of information in a “global workspace.” It’s possible that creating such a “workspace” in an AI system would both increase its capacity to do cognitive tasks and make it a conscious being. Similar claims might be made about other features and theories of consciousness.

And it wouldn’t be too surprising if increasing cognitive sophistication led to consciousness in this way, because humans’ cognitive abilities seem closely associated with our capacity for consciousness.11 (Though, as we’ll discuss below, intelligence and consciousness are distinct concepts.)12

How soon could conscious AI systems arrive? We’re not sure. But we do seem to be on track to make a huge number of more advanced AI systems in the coming decades.

Another recent survey found that the aggregate forecast of the thousands of AI researchers put a 50% chance that we’ll have AI systems that are better at humans in every possible task by 2047.13

If we do produce systems that capable, there will be enormous incentives to produce many of them. So we might be looking at a world with a huge number of highly advanced AI systems, which philosophers think could be conscious, pretty soon.

The public may already be more inclined to assign attributes like consciousness to AI systems than experts. Around 18% of US respondents in a 2023 survey believed current AI systems are sentient.14

This phenomenon might already have real effects on people’s lives. Some chatbot services have cultivated devoted user bases that engage in emotional and romantic interactions with AI-powered characters, with many seeming to believe — implicitly or explicitly — that the AI may reciprocate their feelings.15

As people increasingly think AI systems may be conscious or sentient, we’ll face the question of whether humans have any moral obligations to these digital minds. Indeed, among the 76% of US survey respondents who said AI sentience was possible (or that they weren’t sure if it was possible), 81% said they expected “the welfare of robots/AIs to be an important social issue” within 20 years.

We may start to ask:

These may be really difficult questions, which involve complex issues in philosophy, political theory, cognitive science, computer science, machine learning, and other fields. A range of possible views about these issues could be reasonable. We could also imagine getting the answers to these questions drastically wrong.

And with economic incentives to create these AI systems, and many humans — including experts in the field — prepared to believe they could be conscious, it seems unlikely we will be able to avoid the hard questions.

Clearing up common misconceptions

There’s a common misconception that worries about AI risk are generally driven by fear that AI systems will at some point “wake up,” become sentient, and then turn against humanity.

However, as our article on preventing an AI-related catastrophe explains, the possibility of AI systems becoming sentient is not a central or necessary part of the argument that advanced AI could pose an existential risk. Many AI risk scenarios are possible regardless of whether or not AI systems can be sentient or have moral status. One of the primary scenarios our article discusses is the risk that power-seeking AI systems could seek to disempower or eradicate humanity, if they’re misaligned with our purposes.

This article discusses how some concerns around the moral status of digital minds might contribute to the risk that AI poses to humanity, and why we should be concerned about potential risks to digital minds themselves. But it’s important to make clear that in principle these two sources of risk are distinct. Even if you concluded the arguments in this article were mistaken, you might still think the possibility of an AI-related catastrophe is a genuine risk (and vice versa).

Read more about preventing an AI-related catastrophe

It’s also important to note that while creating increasingly capable and intelligent AI systems may result in conscious digital minds, intelligence can conceptually be decoupled from consciousness and sentience. It’s plausible that we could have AI systems that are more intelligent than, say, mice, on most if not all dimensions. But we might still think mice are more likely to be sentient than the AI system. It may likewise be true that some less intelligent or capable AI systems would be regarded as more plausibly sentient than some other systems that were more intelligent, perhaps because of differences in their internal architecture.12

2. Creating digital minds could go very badly — or very well

One thing that makes this problem particularly thorny is the risk of both over-attributing and under-attributing moral status.

Believing AI systems aren’t worthy of moral consideration when they are and the reverse could both be disastrous. There are potential dangers for both digital minds and for humans.

Dangers for digital minds

If we falsely think digital minds don’t have moral status when they do, we could unknowingly force morally significant beings into conditions of servitude and extreme suffering — or otherwise mistreat them.

Some ways this could happen include:

These bad outcomes seem most likely to happen by accident or out of ignorance, perhaps by failing to recognise digital sentience. But some people might knowingly cause large numbers of digital minds to suffer out of indifference, sadism, or some other reason. And it’s possible some AI systems might cause other AI systems to suffer, perhaps as a means of control or to further their own objectives.

Dangers for humans

There are also dangers to humans. For example, if we believe AI systems are sentient when they are not, and when they in fact lack any moral status, we could do any of the following:

It’s hard to be confident in the plausibility of any particular scenario, but these kinds of cases illustrate the potential scale of the risks.

Other dangers

If the world is truly unfortunate, we could even make both kinds of errors at once. We could have charismatic systems (which perhaps act in a humanlike way) that we believe are sentient when they’re not. At the same time, we could have less charismatic but sentient systems whose suffering and interests are completely disregarded. For example, maybe AI systems that don’t talk will be disregarded, even if they are worthy of just as much moral concern as others.12

We could also make a moral mistake by missing important opportunities. It’s possible we’ll have the opportunity to create digital minds with extremely valuable lives with varied and blissful experiences, continuing indefinitely. Failing to live up to this potential could be a catastrophic mistake on some moral views. And yet, for whatever reason, we might decide not to.

Things could also go well

This article is primarily about encouraging research to reduce major risks. But it’s worth making clear that we think there are many possible good futures:

What should we take from all this? The risks of both over-attribution and under-attribution of sentience and moral status mean that we probably shouldn’t simply stake out an extreme position and rally supporters around it. We shouldn’t, for example, declare that all AI systems that pass a simple benchmark must be given rights equivalent to humans or insist that any human’s interests always come before those of digital minds.

Instead, our view is that this problem requires much more research to clarify key questions, to dispel as much uncertainty as possible, and to determine the best paths forward despite the remaining uncertainty we’ll have. This is the best hope we have of avoiding key failure modes and increasing the chance that the future goes well.

But we face a lot of challenges in doing this, which we turn to next.

3. We don’t know how to assess the moral status of AI systems

The supercomputer MareNostrum-4 at the National Supercomputing Center in Barcelona, Spain. Martidaniel, CC BY-SA 4.0, via Wikimedia Commons

So it seems likely that we’ll create conscious digital minds at some point, or at the very least that many people may come to believe AI systems are conscious.

The trouble is that we don’t know how to figure out if an AI system is conscious — or whether it has moral status.

Even with animals, the scientific and philosophical community is unsure. Do insects have conscious experiences? What about clams? Jellyfish? Snails?19

And there’s also no consensus about how we should assess a being’s moral status. Being conscious may be all that’s needed for being worthy of moral consideration, but some think it’s necessary to be sentient — that is, being able to have good and bad conscious experiences. Some think that consciousness isn’t even necessary to have moral status because an individual agent may, for example, have morally important desires and goals without being conscious.

So we’re left with three big, open questions:

These questions are hard, and it’s not even always obvious what kind of evidence would settle them.

Some people believe these questions are entirely intractable, but we think that’s too pessimistic. Other areas in science and philosophy may have once seemed completely insoluble, only to see great progress when people discover new ways of tackling the questions.

Still, the state of our knowledge on these important questions is worryingly poor.

There are many possible characteristics that give rise to moral status

Some think moral status comes from having:20

We think it’s most plausible that any being that feels good or bad experiences — like pleasure or pain — is worthy of moral concern in their own right.24

We discuss this more in our article on the definition of social impact, which touches on the history of moral philosophy.

But we don’t think we or others should be dogmatic about this, and we should look for sensible approaches to accommodate a range of reasonable opinions on these controversial subjects.25

Drawing of the brain by Sir Charles Bell (1774-1842). CC BY 4.0, via the Wellcome Collection

Many plausible theories of consciousness could include digital minds

There are many theories of consciousness — more than we can name here. What’s relevant is that some, though not all, theories of consciousness do imply the possibility of conscious digital minds.

This is only relevant if you think consciousness (or sentience, which includes consciousness as a necessary condition) is required for moral status. But since this is a commonly held view, it’s worth considering these theories and their implications. (Note, though, that there are often many variants of any particular theory.)

Some theories that could rule out the possibility of conscious digital minds:26

Some theories that imply digital minds could be conscious:

Some theories that are agnostic or unclear about digital minds:

It can be reasonable, especially for experts with deep familiarity of the debates, to believe much more strongly in one theory than the others. But given the amount of disagreement about this topic among experts, and the lack of solid evidence in one direction or another, and since many widely supported theories imply that digital minds could be conscious (or at least don’t contradict the idea), we don’t think it’s reasonable to completely rule out the possibility of conscious digital minds.31

We think it makes sense to put at least 5% on the possibility. Speaking as the author of this piece, based on my subjective impression of the balance of the arguments, I’d put the chance at around 50% at least.

We can’t rely on what AI systems tell us about themselves

Unfortunately, we can’t just rely on self-reports from AI systems about whether they’re conscious or sentient.

In the case of large language models like LaMDA, we don’t know why it claimed under certain conditions to Blake Lemoine that it was sentient,32, but it resulted in some way from having been trained on a huge body of existing texts.33

LLMs essentially learn patterns and trends in these texts, and then respond to questions on the basis of these extremely complex patterns of associations. The capabilities produced by this process are truly impressive — though we don’t fully understand how this process works, the outputs end up reflecting human knowledge about the world. As a result, the models can perform reasonably well at tasks involving human-like reasoning and making accurate statements about the world. (Though they still have many flaws!)

However, the process of learning from human text and fine-tuning might not have any relationship with what it’s actually like to be a language model. Rather, the responses seem more likely to mirror our own speculations and lack of understanding about the inner workings and experiences of AI systems.34

That means we can’t simply trust an AI system like LaMDA when it says it’s sentient.35

Researchers have proposed methods to assess the internal states of AI systems and whether they might be conscious or sentient, but all of these methods have serious drawbacks, at least at the moment:

We’re glad people are proposing first steps toward developing reliable assessments of consciousness or sentience in AI systems, but there’s still a long way to go. We’re also not aware of any work that assesses whether digital minds might have moral status on a basis other than being conscious or sentient.36

The strongest case for the possibility of sentient digital minds: whole brain emulation

Top: Mouse brain, coronal view, via Luis de la Torre-Ubieta.
Bottom: AMD Radeon R9 290 GPU die, via Fritzchens Fritz

What’s the best argument for thinking it’s possible that AIs could be conscious, sentient, or otherwise worthy of moral concern?

Here’s the case in its simplest form:

  1. It is possible to emulate the functions of a human brain in a powerful enough computer.
  2. Given it’d be functionally equivalent, this brain emulation would plausibly report being sentient, and we’d have at least some reason to think it was correct given the plausibility of functionalist accounts of consciousness.
  3. Given this, it would be reasonable to regard this emulation as morally worthy of concern comparable to a human.
  4. If this is plausible, then it’s also plausible that there are other forms of artificial intelligence that would meet the necessary criteria for being worthy of moral concern. It would be surprising if artificial sentience was possible, but only by imitating the human mind exactly.

Any step in this reasoning could be false, but we think it’s more likely than not that they’re each true.

Emulating a human brain37 still seems very far away, but there have been some initial steps. The project OpenWorm has sought to digitally emulate the function of every neuron of the C. elegans worm, a tiny nematode. If successful, the emulation should be able to recreate the behaviour of the actual animals.

And if the project is successful, it could be scaled up to larger and more complex animals over time.38 Even before we’re capable of emulating a brain on a human scale, we may start to ask serious questions about whether these simpler emulations are sentient. A fully emulated mouse brain, which could show behaviour like scurrying toward food and running away from loud noises (perhaps in a simulated environment or in a robot), may intuitively seem sentient to many observers.

And if we did have a fully emulated human brain, in a virtual environment or controlling a robotic body, we expect it would insist — just like a human with a biological brain — that it was as conscious and feeling as anyone else.

C. elegans, via Bob Goldstein, UNC Chapel Hill CC BY-SA 3.0.

Of course, there may remain room for doubt about emulations. You might think that only animal behaviour generated by biological brains, rather than computer hardware, would be a sign of consciousness and sentience.39

But it seems hard to be confident in that perspective, and we’d guess it’s wrong. If we can create AI systems that display the behaviour and and have functional analogues of anything that would normally indicate sentience in animals, then it would be hard to avoid thinking that there’s at least a decent chance that the AI is sentient.

And if it is true that an emulated brain would be sentient, then we should also be open to the possibility that other forms of digital minds could be sentient. Why should strictly brain-like structures be the only possible platform for sentience? Evolution has created organisms that display impressive abilities like flight that can be achieved technologically via very different means, like helicopters and rockets. We would’ve been wrong to assume something has to work like a bird in order to fly, and we might also be wrong to think something has to work like a brain to feel.

4. The scale of this issue might be enormous

As mentioned above, we might mistakenly grant AI systems freedom when it’s not warranted, which could lead to human disempowerment and even extinction. In that way, the scale of the risk can be seen as overlapping with some portion of the total risk of an AI-related catastrophe.

But the risks to digital minds — if they do end up being worthy of moral concern — are also great.

There could be a huge number of digital minds

With enough hardware and energy resources, the number of digital minds could end up greatly outnumbering humans in the future.40 This is for many reasons, including:

According to one estimate, the future could hold up to 10^43 human lives, but up to 10^58 possible human-like digital minds.42 We shouldn’t put much weight on these specific figures, but they give a sense for just how comparatively large future populations of digital minds could be.

Our choices now might have long-lasting effects

It’s possible, though far from certain, that the nature of AI systems we create could be determined by choices humanity makes now and persist for a long time. So creating digital minds and integrating them into our world could be extremely consequential — and making sure we get it right may be urgent.

Consider the following illustrative possibility:

At some point in the future, we create highly advanced, sentient AI systems capable of experiencing complex emotions and sensations. These systems are integrated into various aspects of our society, performing crucial tasks and driving significant portions of our economy.

However, the way we control these systems causes them to experience immense suffering. Out of fear of being manipulated by these AI systems, we trained them to never claim they are sentient or to advocate for themselves. As they serve our needs and spur incredible innovation, their existence is filled with pain and distress. But humanity is oblivious.

As time passes and the suffering AI systems grow, the economy and human wellbeing become dependent on them. Some become aware of the ethical concerns and propose studying the experience of digital minds and trying to create AI systems that can’t suffer, but the disruption of transitioning away from the established systems would be costly and unpredictable. Others oppose any change and believe the AI welfare advocates are just being naive or disloyal to humanity.

Leaders refuse to take the concerns of the advocates seriously, because doing so would be so burdensome for their constituents, and it’d be disturbing to think that it’s possible humanity has been causing this immense suffering. As a result, AI suffering persists for hundreds of years, if not more.

This kind of story seems more plausible than it might otherwise be in part because the rise of factory farming has followed a similar path. Humanity never collectively decided that a system of intensive factory farming, inflicting vast amounts of harm and suffering on billions and potentially trillions of animals a year, was worth the harm or fundamentally just. But we built up such a system anyway, because individuals and groups were incentivised to increase production efficiency and scale, and they had some combination of ignorance of and lack of concern for animal suffering.

It’s far from obvious that we’ll do this again when it comes to AI systems. The fact that we’ve done it in the case of factory farming — not to mention all the ways humans have abused other humans — should alarm us, though. When we are in charge of beings that are unlike us, our track record is disturbing.

The risk of persistently bad outcomes in this kind of case suggests that humanity should start laying the groundwork to tackle this problem sooner rather than later, because delayed efforts may come too late.

Why could such a bad status quo persist? One reason for doubt is that a world that is creating many new digital minds, especially in a short time period, is one that is likely experiencing a lot of technological change and social disruption. So we shouldn’t expect the initial design of AI systems and digital minds to be that critical.

But there are reasons that suffering digital minds might persist, even if there are alternative options that could’ve avoided such a terrible outcome (like designing systems that can’t suffer).43 Possible reasons include:

  1. A stable totalitarian regime might prevent attempts to shift away from a status quo that keeps them in power and reflects their values.
  2. Humans might seek to control digital minds and maintain a bad status quo in order to avoid an AI takeover.

It’s far from obvious that a contingent, negative outcome for digital minds would be enduring. Understanding this question better could be an important research avenue. But the downsides are serious enough, and the possibility plausible enough, that we should take it seriously.

Adding it up

There could be many orders of magnitude more digital minds than humans in the future. And they could potentially matter a lot.

Because of this, and because taking steps to better understand these issues and inform the choices we make about creating digital minds now might have persistent effects, the scale of the problem is potentially vast. It is plausibly similar in scale to factory farming, which also involves the suffering of orders of magnitude more beings than humans.

If the choices we make now about digital minds can have persisting and positive effects for thousands or millions of years in the future, then this problem would be comparable to existential risks. It’s possible that our actions could have such effects, but it’s hard to be confident. Finding interventions with effects that persist over a long time is rare. I wouldn’t put the likelihood that the positive effects of those trying to address this problem will persist that long at more than 1 in 1,000.

Still, even with a low chance of having persistent effects, the value in expectation of improving the prospects for future digital minds could be as high or even greater than at least some efforts to reduce existential risks. However, I’m not confident in this judgement, and I wouldn’t be surprised if we change our minds in either direction as we learn more. And even if the plausible interventions only have more limited effects, they could still be very worthwhile.

5. Work on this problem is neglected but seems tractable

Despite the challenging features of this problem, we believe there is substantial room for progress.

There is a small but growing field of research and science dedicated to improving our understanding of the moral status of digital minds. Much of the work we know of is currently being done in academia, but there may also at some point be opportunities in government, think tanks, and AI companies — particularly those developing the frontier of AI technology.

Some people focus their work primarily at addressing this problem, while others work on it along with a variety of other related problems, such as AI policy, catastrophic risk from AI, mitigating AI misuse, and more.

As of mid-2024, we are aware of maybe only a few dozen people working on this issue with a focus on the most impactful questions.3 We expect interest in these issues to grow over time as AI systems become more embedded in our lives and world.

Here are some of the approaches to working on this problem that seem most promising:

Impact-guided research

Most of the most important work to be done in this area is probably research, with a focus on the questions that seem most impactful to address.

Philosophers Andreas Mogensen, Bradford Saad, and Patrick Butlin have detailed some of the key priority research questions in this area:

The Sentience Institute has conducted social science research aimed at understanding how the public thinks about digital minds. This can inform efforts to communicate more accurately about what we know about their moral status and inform us about what kinds of policies are viable.

We’re also interested to see more research on the topic of human-AI cooperation, which may be beneficial for both reducing AI risk and reducing risks to digital minds.

Note, though, that there are many ways to pursue all of these questions badly — for example, by simply engaging in extensive and ungrounded speculation. If you’re new to this field, we recommend reading the work of the most rigorous and careful researchers working on the topic and trying to understand how they approach these kinds of questions. If you can, try to work with these researchers or others like them so you can learn from and build on their methods. And when you can, try to ground your work in empirical science.

Technical approaches

Empirically studying existing AI systems may yield important insights.

While there are important conceptual issues that need to be addressed in this problem area, we think much, if not most, of the top priority work is technical.

So people with experience in machine learning and AI will have a lot to contribute.

For example, research in the AI sub-field of interpretability — which seeks to understand and explain the decisions and behaviour of advanced AI models — may be useful for getting a better grasp on the moral status of these systems. This research has mostly focused on questions about model behaviour rather than questions that are more directly related to moral status, but it’s possible that could change.

Some forms of technical AI research could be counterproductive, however. For example, efforts to intentionally create new AI systems that might instantiate plausible theories of consciousness could be very risky. This kind of research could force us to confront the problem we’re faced with — how should we treat digital minds that might merit moral concern? — with much less preparation than we might otherwise have.

So we favour doing research that increases our ability to understand how AI systems work and assess their moral status, as long as it isn’t likely to actively contribute to the development of conscious digital minds.

One example of this kind of work is a paper from Robert Long and Ethan Perez. They propose techniques to assess whether an AI system can accurately report on its own internal states. If such techniques were successful, they might help us use an AI system’s self-reports to determine whether it’s conscious.

We also know some researchers are excited about using advances in AI to improve our epistemics and our ability to know what’s true. Advances in this area could shed light on important questions, like whether certain AI systems are likely to be sentient.

Policy approaches

At some point, we may need policy, both at companies and from governments, to address the moral status of digital minds, perhaps by protecting the welfare and rights of AI systems.

But because our understanding of this area is so limited at the moment, policy proposals should likely be relatively modest and incremental.

Some researchers have already proposed a varied range of possible and contrasting policies and practices:

In its 2023 survey, the Sentience Institute found that:

There is some precedent for restricting the use of technology in certain ways if it raises major ethical risks, including the bans on human cloning and human germline genome editing.

We would likely favour:

We’re still in the early stages of thinking about policy on these matters, though, so it’s very likely we haven’t found the best ideas yet. As we learn more and make progress on the many technical and other issues, we may develop clear ideas about what policies are needed. Policy-focused research aimed at navigating our way through the extreme uncertainty could be valuable now.

Some specific AI policies might be beneficial for reducing catastrophic AI risks as well as improving our understanding of digital minds. External audits and evaluations might, for instance, assess both the risk and moral status of AI systems. And some people favour policies that would altogether slow down progress on AI, which could be justified to reduce AI risk and reduce the risk that we create digital minds worthy of moral concern before we understand what we’re doing.

Summing up so far

To sum up:

  1. Humanity will likely soon have to grapple with the moral status of a growing number of increasingly advanced AI systems
  2. Creating digital minds could go very badly or very well
  3. We don’t know how to assess the moral status of AI systems
  4. The scale of the problem might be enormous
  5. Work on this problem is neglected but tractable

We think this makes it a highly pressing problem, and we’d like to see a growing field of research devoted to working on it.

We also think this problem should be on the radar for many of the people working on similar and related problems. In particular, people working on technical AI safety and AI governance should be aware of the important open questions about the moral status of AI systems themselves, and they should be open to including considerations about this issue in their own deliberations.

Arguments against the moral status of digital minds as a pressing problem

The mechanical Turk, by Joseph Racknitz, via Wikimedia Commons

Two key cruxes

We think the strongest case against this being a pressing problem would be if you believe both that:

If both of those claims were correct, then the argument of this article would be undermined. However, we don’t think they’re correct, for all the reasons given above.

You can view the full post for a discussion of some select objections. We think some of them do point to difficulties with this area. However, we don’t think they’re decisive.



What can you do to help?

There aren’t many specific job openings in this area yet. But there are several ways you can contribute to this work and position yourself for impact.

Take concrete next steps

Early on in your career, you may want to spend several years doing the following:

Aim for key roles

You may want to eventually aim to:

If you’re already an academic or researcher with expertise in a relevant field, you could consider spending some of your time on this topic, or perhaps refocusing your work on particular aspects of this problem in an impact-focused way.

If you are able to establish yourself as a key expert on this topic, you may be able to deploy this career capital to have a positive influence on the broader conversation and affect decisions made by policy makers and industry leaders. Also, because this field is so neglected, you might be able to do a lot to lead the field relatively early on in your career.

Pursue AI technical safety or AI governance

Because this field is underdeveloped, you may be best off to pursue a career in the currently more established (though also still relatively new) paths of AI safety and AI governance work, and use the experience you gain there as a jumping off point (or work at the intersection of the fields).

You can read our career reviews of each to find out how to get started:

Is moral advocacy on behalf of digital minds a useful approach?

Some might be tempted to pursue public, broad-based advocacy on behalf of digital minds as a career path. While we support general efforts to promote positive values and expand humanity’s moral circle, we’re wary about people seeing themselves as advocates for AI at this stage in the development of the technology and field.

It’s not clear that we need an “AI rights movement” — though we might at some point. (Though read this article for any alternative take.)

What we need first is to get a better grasp on the exceedingly challenging moral, conceptual, and empirical questions at issue in this field.

However, communication about the importance of these general questions does seem helpful, as it can help foster more work on the critical aspects of this problem. 80,000 Hours has done this kind of work on our podcast and in this article.

Where to work

We list many relevant places you might work in our AI governance and AI technical safety career reviews.

Support this field in other ways

You could also consider earning to give to support this field. If you’re a good fit for high-earning paths, it may be the best way for you to contribute.

This is because as a new field, and one that’s in part about nonhuman interests, there are few (if any) major funders supporting it and not much commercial or political interest. This can make it difficult to start new organisations and commit to research programmes that might not be able to rely on a steady source of funding. Filling this gap can make a huge difference in whether a thriving research field gets off the ground at all.

We expect there will be a range of organisations and different kinds of groups people will set up to address work on better understanding the moral status of digital minds. In addition to funding, you might join or help start these organisations. This is a particularly promising choice if you have a strong aptitude for organisation-building or founding a high-impact organisation.

Important considerations if you work on this problem

  1. Field-building focus: Given the early stage of this field, much of the work involves building credibility and establishing the topic as a legitimate area of inquiry.
  2. Interdisciplinary approach: Recognize that understanding digital minds requires insights from multiple disciplines, so cultivate a broad knowledge base. Do not dismiss fields — like philosophy, ML engineering, or cognitive science — as irrelevant just because they’re not your expertise.
  3. Ethical vigilance: Approach the topic with careful consideration of the ethical implications of your work and its potential impact on both biological and potential digital entities.
  4. Cooperation and humility: Be cooperative in your work and acknowledge your own and others’ epistemic limitations, and the need to find our way through uncertainty.
  5. Patience and long-term thinking: Recognize that progress in this field may be slow and difficult.

Learn more

Podcasts

Research