Only Aggregationists Respect the Separateness of Persons
By Richard Y Chappellđ¸ @ 2025-08-15T15:25 (+12)
This is a linkpost to https://www.goodthoughts.blog/p/only-aggregationists-respect-the
Separate people have independent value
I often find myself thinking that the conventional wisdom in moral philosophy gets a lot of things backwards. For example, Iâve previously discussed how deontology is much more deeply self-effacing (making objectively right actions, and not just bungled attempts to act rightly, lamentable) than consequentialism. In this post, Iâll explain why I think that only âaggregationistâ viewsâon which five people being tortured to death is five times worse (all else equal) than just one person suffering this awful fateâfully respect the separateness of persons.
Ethics as Normative Psychology
First, some background. Normative ethics can be understood as specifying what psychological attitudes are warranted towards different objects. To say that life is good is to say that it warrants desire or similar pro-attitudes (in an idealized sense that abstracts away from our cognitive limitations).
So to say that each personâs well-being is a separate, non-fungible good, is to say that we should (ideally) have distinct non-instrumental desires for each personâs well-being. (This is the core idea of my âValue Receptaclesâ paper.)
You could imagine a kind of utilitarian who fails to do this: someone who just has a single desire to maximize aggregate welfare, and sees each person as a constitutive means to this end, just as individual dollar bills are mere constitutive means to your aggregate wealth (you donât care about the bills as individualsâthey are replaceable without regret). Then, rather than feeling torn when forced to choose between two equally worthy lives, this agent would feel stark indifference: the choice of which life to save would seem no more significant to them than the choice between a $20 bill or two tens. I think it would be obscene to view human lives as fungible in this way, so I show how to understand utilitarianism in a way that avoids this flaw (but still allows you to make trade-offsâyou can retain commensurability without fungibility). By having separate desires for each personâs well-being, my token-pluralistic utilitarian values each person separately in the most literal sense, and this is reflected psychologically in their (i) feeling the loss whenever an individual is harmed, and (ii) feeling a different loss (due to a different desire of theirs being thwarted) depending on which individual is harmed.
In what follows, Iâll argue that anti-aggregationists fail to value people independently in this way.
Belief-Desire Psychology and Independent Desires
Two of the most important kinds of mental states (as inputs to rational choice and action) are beliefs and desires. Beliefs aim at truth, representing how we take the world to be. Desires aim at the good (or desirable), representing how we want the world to be. Epistemology addresses questions about what we ought to believe; ethics is (most fundamentally) about what we ought to want.
Some of our desires are not entirely independent of each other. I may want some chocolate; I may want some fudge; but if one of these desires is satisfied, I may cease to want the other treat. (Maybe what I really wanted is just âsomething sufficiently tastyâ, and the fudge and chocolate are at least partly-fungible means to this common end.)
Or I may also want to go for a nice walk in the woods, but not after eating a large meal. In this case, thereâs no substitution effect; itâs more of a conflict. The walk wouldnât be âniceâ if I was feeling overgorged at the time. But thatâs a purely instrumental form of interaction; really the two desires maintain a deeper sort of independence, or so Iâm inclined to think.
Hereâs a possible test: suppose I could separate out the two events to minimize causal interactions and keep âall else equalâ, as is best practice for thought experiments. Would enjoying a walk one day do anything to undermine the desirability of enjoying a chocolatey desert the next day (or vice versa)? Presumably not. We could imagine some strange person for whom the two acted as substitutes, but if I really value both separately and independently (as I take myself to do), then Iâll much prefer the prospect of satisfying both desires (over time) rather than just one of them.
This may all seem truistic. Of course we prefer to satisfy more of our desires rather than fewer. Thatâs just what it is to want all the things rather than just, say, a disjunction of themâlike fudge or chocolate. In effect, what weâre observing here is that independent desires aggregate. If you have âtwo desiresâ that donât aggregate in this way, that would seem to indicate that they arenât actually independent, fundamental desires. Maybe theyâre just two fungible means to satisfying one deeper desire. (Remember this in what follows. Itâs key to understanding whatâs perverse about moral anti-aggregationism.)
Anti-Aggregationists Donât Separately Desire Each Personâs Well-being
So hereâs something I find deeply appalling about anti-aggregationists: They donât want all the morally good things! For example, after offering a kind of contractualist justification of aggregation,[1] Flo writes:
Still, the reason you should help more instead of fewer is not because thereâs a bunch of âintrinsic valueâ in the world that globs together to form an even bigger intrinsic value that youâre supposed to care about even more. Good is still good-for, and goodness of states of affairs is just an approximate way of talking about our obligations. This is why I donât feel like the emotional appeals utilitarians on here use against non-consequentialism are very forceful. âYou would save the five over David, but you wouldnât steal the drug from him to save the five? You care about some magical metaphysical relation between a person and their âpropertyâ more than peopleâs lives?â No, the case gives no evidence as to how much I value peopleâs lives; an innocent individual dies in either case. Nobody is having a five-times-worse outcome inflicted upon them by my choice not to steal. I do care about property rights more than I care about imaginary aggregations of goodness, though.
This is a lovely summary of what I take to be a common perspective among non-consequentialists. I expect plenty of moral philosophers would sign on to this statement. So I donât mean to be picking on Flo in particular when I say: this whole framing of the dispute is hopelessly confused.
Good depends on good-for, as welfarists claim. But if you refuse to move from claims about âgood forâ to âgoodâ (or desirable) simpliciter, you are implicitly refusing to care about more than one person at once, or to recognize that multiple people matter independently. (This is the presupposition behind taking it to be relevant that âNobody is having a five-times-worse outcome inflicted upon them.â Why else would anyone think that all the badness had to be contained within one life in order for it to matter? You cannot recognize the full horror of the Holocaust by only looking at a single victim in isolation. Every other victim matters in addition. To deny this would be stark moral insanity.)
Of course, nobody should care fundamentally about âbig globs of intrinsic valueâ or âimaginary aggregations of goodnessâ. What you should care about is concrete people (plural), and you should care about each person separately and independently. What that meansâin consequence of having multiple genuinely independent desiresâis that a rational agent with the prescribed desires will want more people to be saved rather than fewer. (Notice that an agent with this plurality of desires receives five times as much desire-satisfaction in the event that five lives are saved rather than just one.)[2] People arenât like fudge and chocolate, where any one will suffice. Each person matters independently of the others.
What does the anti-aggregationist agent desire, by comparison? Weâre told that whether one person dies or five, âan innocent individual dies in either case.â It sounds like the desire(s) corresponding to this view must be much more generic and binary. Whereas I think an ideal agent would care about each person separately, the anti-aggregationist agent (suggested by the quoted passage) appears to treat fixed-level harmful outcomes for different peopleâand even different numbers of people, each experiencing the full fixed level of harmâas entirely fungible. So long as no individual is âhaving a five-times-worse outcome inflicted upon them,â adding another victim doesnât register as a morally significant difference. This seems⌠less than ideal!
The anti-aggregationist basically has their moral concern exhausted by a single generic desire that the worst-off position be less awful. We should, of course, all wish better for the worst-off individual. But if that is your only moral desire then you are failing to care about every other person in the world.
To make the contrast more concrete, consider who is more morally ideal:
Aggregating Amy: separately desires each personâs flourishing.
Generic Jim: literally only wants one thing and itâs fucking disgusting maximin.[3]
Now, I cannot understand how anyone could seriously claim that Generic Jim is more virtuous than Amy (let alone how they could claim to thereby be respecting the separateness of persons better than a utilitarian who holds up Amy as their moral ideal). Jim stops caring about someoneâs suffering the moment he finds someone else who is worse off! He fails to treat each personâs suffering as mattering in its own rightâmaintaining its full force and independent moral significance no matter what is going on with other people. All that matters to him is that someone is suffering a fixed-level harm; it doesnât even matter how many people suffer so.
This anti-aggregationist pattern of concern involves caring about a single de dicto role (âthe worst offâ) rather than caring about each and every concrete person. Amy wants each person to flourish rather than suffer, and her (equally-weighted) desires aggregate in such a way that sheâlike any decent personâis more bothered the more people who suffer and die. Conversely, the more people get to flourish, the more the world is to her liking. She doesnât only look at one person and let their well-being settle her overall attitude towards the state of affairs. To truly care about everyone, you have to let everyone play a (sufficiently significant) role in your cognitive economy, shaping your overall verdictive attitudes. Only aggregationists do this.[4]
What is going on in moral philosophy?
When you look at it this way, it seems wild that anti-aggregationists managed to turn caring about fewer people into a putative virtue. I think the problem is that moral philosophers donât think enough in telic terms, about what desires or preferences their moral theory âcorresponds toâ or renders objectively fitting.
Deontologists may implicitly be starting from a picture on which the moral agent has primarily self-interested concerns, along with a compensatingâperhaps even overridingâdesire to act rightly (or at least to avoid acting wrongly). Given this background picture, itâs natural to see the moral theoristâs job as being to spell out what considerations make acts right or wrong, which can then hook up to this explicit deontic concern in the moral agent. Itâs all very abstract, which can easily lead one into absurdity (as I think has happened with anti-aggregationism being wholly motivated by philosophical confusions). But the thing I find most striking is how this methodology starts from assuming a kind of vicious lack of concern for others, which then needs to be âcorrectedâ by means of explicit deontic moralizing.
This is not my conception of ethics at all. We do eventually need to offer guidance to imperfectly virtuous people, of course. Iâm on board with that. But ethics neednât start there, as I donât think the ideal agent would engage in explicit moralizing at all. Rather, they would (as Aristotle suggested) simply want to do the right thing, for the right reasons. So I think itâs illuminating to start our theorizing by thinking about what that virtuous ideal would look like.
Once we attend to this question, it just seems undeniable that the benevolent utilitarian saint (Amy) is a much better person than the anti-aggregationist Jim (with his generic desire for the pattern of the world to satisfy maximin, and no independent desires for everyone elseâs flourishing). Iâm especially struck by the sheer moral stinginess of Jimâs generic and limited concern, in contrast to the overflowing abundance of good will that Amy directs towards every single one of us, a concern for our well-being that she maintains no matter who else is in the situation or what is going on with them. In maintaining an independent desire for our flourishing, Amy respects our separate value in a way that Jim does not.
Iâm really curious whether, after reflecting on the psychologies of these two hypothetical agents, any anti-aggregationists out there really want to say that Jim is more virtuous after all, and if so how they would make that sound remotely plausible.
Coda: On the significance of âseparate personsâ talk
I can predict that many deontologists reading this post will react with the thought: âThatâs not what we mean when we talk about the separateness of persons!â But letâs pause to think about what is worth talking about in this vicinity. Here are various candidate thoughts that different philosophers might (with varying degrees of warrant) take to be âpre-theoretic truismsâ that an adequate moral theory should satisfy:
(1) A large harm or benefit to one cannot be outweighed by any number of smaller harms or benefits to many.
(2) Inter-personal trade-offs are harder to justify than intra-personal ones.
(3) Individual persons are morally âseparateâ in the sense that they should be valued in themselves and independently of each other (rather than, for example, having moral agents regard individuals as fungibleâreplaceable without regretâin the way that dollar bills are).
Of these three claims, I think only (3) truly deserves to be considered a âtruismâ that it would be embarrassing for a theory to violate. (1) and (2) are, I think, false.[5] Even if you think theyâre true, thereâs no obvious reason why a consequentialist should feel any pressure to share your verdict. So those principles seem like a poor basis for âobjectingâ to consequentialism. (3), by contrast, seems like the kind of principle that a decent theory needs to accommodate. âYour theory doesnât respect the independent value of individual personsâ is clearly a criticism, marking a theory out as not just yielding incorrect extensional verdicts about cases, but as deeply disrespectful in a way that is plausibly disqualifying.
I also think that, of the three options, (3) is clearly the closest match to the plain literal meaning of ârespecting the separateness of personsâ, so anyone using the latter phrase to instead stipulatively mean (1) or (2) is being gratuitously confusing. Worse, I think theyâre rhetorically exploiting the ordinary meaningâassociated with (3)âas a kind of âmotte and baileyâ, retreating to the stipulative definitions once itâs explained how utilitarianism doesnât actually violate the separateness of persons in sense (3).
So, even if most moral philosophers have now come to use the term to mean (1) or (2), I think they should reconsider their usage. It is both more accurate and more philosophically significant to say thatâin virtue of meaning (3)âvalue-denying anti-aggregationists fail to respect the separateness of persons. Contrary to the conventional wisdom in moral philosophy, the separate value of distinct persons is best respected by utilitarians and others who recognizeâand aggregateâthe value of each and every individual, while nonetheless holding the value of the individuals to be more fundamental than that of their aggregate. (We care about maximizing aggregate value because we care about all the individuals we thereby benefit, not vice versa.)
- ^
Itâs a good argument (and could even be taken further)! But still not sufficient for true virtue, sorry.
- ^
Donât confuse this observation with the tautological egoistâs attribution that the agent âonly cares aboutâ their own desire-satisfaction. The agentâs concerns are given by the contents of their fundamental desires, which here concern the well-being of other people. Good stuff, nothing selfish about it.
- ^
Maximin = making the worst-off position as well-off as possible.
- ^
Scanlonâs argument for numbers as tie-breakers hints in this directionâhe notes it would seem disrespectful to a second person you could save if you didnât treat their life or death as giving you any more reason to save the group than you would have had from the first person in the group alone. What Iâm now suggesting is that this doesnât go far enough. If you say that the importance of saving the second person is reduced at all by the presence of the first person, you have failed to value the two people separately and independently.
- ^
I donât even think itâs âbullet-bitingâ to say so. I think (1) is obviously false, and (2) just doesnât seem intuitively obvious either wayâit seems like the kind of thing we should determine by doing some moral theorizing and seeing what we find. As it happens, I think inter-personal cases are significantly different, in that they have more reasons going in both directions (balancing out to make the tradeoff neither harder nor easier to justify, but creating a sense of âhigher stakesâ with greater angst).
SummaryBot @ 2025-08-15T15:41 (+2)
Executive summary: The author argues that only aggregationist moral theoriesâthose that sum the value of each personâs well-beingâtruly respect the separateness of persons, because they require caring about each individualâs welfare independently, whereas anti-aggregationist views implicitly treat additional peopleâs suffering as morally irrelevant once a worst-off individual is identified.
Key points:
- Independent value requires independent desires: To genuinely value separate persons, one must have distinct, non-fungible desires for each personâs well-being; this leads naturally to aggregation, since satisfying more such desires is better.
- Anti-aggregationist psychology is morally stingy: By focusing only on the worst-off individual (e.g., via maximin), anti-aggregationists neglect the independent moral significance of othersâ suffering or flourishing.
- Illustrative contrast: âAggregating Amyâ cares equally and separately about each personâs flourishing, whereas âGeneric Jimâ stops caring about others once someone worse-off is foundâmaking Amy the more virtuous moral ideal.
- Misuse of âseparateness of personsâ: Philosophers often use the phrase to defend principles like âlarge harms to one outweigh many small harmsâ or âinterpersonal trade-offs are harder,â but the author claims the more important and literal sense is valuing each person independently.
- Utilitarianism accommodates true separateness: Properly framed, utilitarianism values individuals first and the aggregate secondâcaring about the total only because each personâs welfare counts in its own right.
- Conventional wisdom reversal: Contrary to common deontological critiques, it is anti-aggregationistsânot aggregationistsâwho fail to respect the separate value of distinct persons.
This comment was auto-generated by the EA Forum Team. Feel free to point out issues with this summary by replying to the comment, and contact us if you have feedback.